跳转到内容

用户:Willy1018/沙盒3

维基百科,自由的百科全书

Template:Other uses of

Template:Classical mechanics

The flow of sand in an hourglass can be used to measure the passage of time. It also concretely represents the present as being between the past and the future.

Time is the indefinite continued progress of existence and events that occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future.[1][2][3] Time is a component quantity of various measurements used to sequence events, to compare the duration of events or the intervals between them, and to quantify rates of change of quantities in material reality or in the conscious experience.[4][5][6][7] Time is often referred to as the fourth dimension, along with the three spatial dimensions.[8]

Time has long been an important subject of study in religion, philosophy, and science, but defining it in a manner applicable to all fields without circularity has consistently eluded scholars.[2][6][7][9][10][11] Nevertheless, diverse fields such as business, industry, sports, the sciences, and the performing arts all incorporate some notion of time into their respective measuring systems.[12][13][14] Two contrasting viewpoints on time divide prominent philosophers. One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the universe—a dimension independent of events, in which events occur in sequence. Sir Isaac Newton subscribed to this realist view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as Newtonian time.[15][16] The opposing view is that time does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with space and number) within which humans sequence and compare events. This second view, in the tradition of Gottfried Leibniz[17] and Immanuel Kant,[18][19] holds that time is neither an event nor a thing, and thus is not itself measurable nor can it be travelled.

Time in physics is unambiguously operationally defined as "what a clock reads."[6][17][20] Time is one of the seven fundamental physical quantities in both the International System of Units and International System of Quantities. Time is used to define other quantities—such as velocity—so defining time in terms of such quantities would result in circularity of definition.[21] An operational definition of time, wherein one says that observing a certain number of repetitions of one or another standard cyclical event (such as the passage of a free-swinging pendulum) constitutes one standard unit such as the second, is highly useful in the conduct of both advanced experiments and everyday affairs of life. The operational definition leaves aside the question whether there is something called time, apart from the counting activity just mentioned, that flows and that can be measured. Investigations of a single continuum called spacetime bring questions about space into questions about time, questions that have their roots in the works of early students of natural philosophy.

Furthermore, it may be that there is a subjective component to time, but whether or not time itself is "felt", as a sensation, or is a judgment, is a matter of debate.[2][6][7][22][23]

Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and technologists, and was a prime motivation in navigation and astronomy. Periodic events and periodic motion have long served as standards for units of time. Examples include the apparent motion of the sun across the sky, the phases of the moon, the swing of a pendulum, and the beat of a heart. Currently, the international unit of time, the second, is defined by measuring the electronic transition frequency of caesium atoms (see below). Time is also of significant social importance, having economic value ("time is money") as well as personal value, due to an awareness of the limited time in each day and in human life spans.

Temporal measurement and history

[编辑]

Generally speaking, methods of temporal measurement, or chronometry, take two distinct forms: the calendar, a mathematical tool for organizing intervals of time,[24] and the clock, a physical mechanism that counts the passage of time. In day-to-day life, the clock is consulted for periods less than a day whereas the calendar is consulted for periods longer than a day. Increasingly, personal electronic devices display both calendars and clocks simultaneously. The number (as on a clock dial or calendar) that marks the occurrence of a specified event as to hour or date is obtained by counting from a fiducial epoch—a central reference point.

History of the calendar

[编辑]

Artifacts from the Paleolithic suggest that the moon was used to reckon time as early as 6,000 years ago.[25] Lunar calendars were among the first to appear, either 12 or 13 lunar months (either 354 or 384 days). Without intercalation to add days or months to some years, seasons quickly drift in a calendar based solely on twelve lunar months. Lunisolar calendars have a thirteenth month added to some years to make up for the difference between a full year (now known to be about 365.24 days) and a year of just twelve lunar months. The numbers twelve and thirteen came to feature prominently in many cultures, at least partly due to this relationship of months to years. Other early forms of calendars originated in Mesoamerica, particularly in ancient Mayan civilization. These calendars were religiously and astronomically based, with 18 months in a year and 20 days in a month.[26]

The reforms of Julius Caesar in 45 BC put the Roman world on a solar calendar. This Julian calendar was faulty in that its intercalation still allowed the astronomical solstices and equinoxes to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. Pope Gregory XIII introduced a correction in 1582; the Gregorian calendar was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but it is now the most commonly used calendar around the world, by far.

During the French Revolution, a new clock and calendar were invented in attempt to de-Christianize time and create a more rational system in order to replace the Gregorian Calendar. The French Republican Calendar's days consisted of ten hours of a hundred minutes of a hundred seconds, which marked a deviation from the duodecimal system used in many other devices by many cultures. The system was later abolished in 1806.[27]

History of time measurement devices

[编辑]
Horizontal sundial in Taganrog

A large variety of devices has been invented to measure time. The study of these devices is called horology.

An Egyptian device that dates to c.1500 BC, similar in shape to a bent T-square, measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a nonlinear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At noon, the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.[28]

A sundial uses a gnomon to cast a shadow on a set of markings calibrated to the hour. The position of the shadow marks the hour in local time. The idea to separate the day into smaller parts is credited to Egyptians because of their sundials, which operated on a duodecimal system based in the number 12. The importance of the number 12 is due the number of lunar cycles in a year and the number of stars used to count the passage of night.[29]

The most precise timekeeping device of the ancient world was the water clock, or clepsydra, one of which was found in the tomb of Egyptian pharaoh Amenhotep I (1525–1504 BC). They could be used to measure the hours even at night, but required manual upkeep to replenish the flow of water. The Ancient Greeks and the people from Chaldea (southeastern Mesopotamia) regularly maintained timekeeping records as an essential part of their astronomical observations. Arab inventors and engineers in particular made improvements on the use of water clocks up to the Middle Ages.[30] In the 11th century, Chinese inventors and engineers invented the first mechanical clocks driven by an escapement mechanism.

A contemporary quartz watch, 2007

The hourglass uses the flow of sand to measure the flow of time. They were used in navigation. Ferdinand Magellan used 18 glasses on each ship for his circumnavigation of the globe (1522).[31] Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Waterclocks, and later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. Richard of Wallingford (1292–1336), abbot of St. Alban's abbey, famously built a mechanical clock as an astronomical orrery about 1330.[32][33] Great advances in accurate time-keeping were made by Galileo Galilei and especially Christiaan Huygens with the invention of pendulum driven clocks along with the invention of the minute hand by Jost Burgi.[34]

The English word clock probably comes from the Middle Dutch word klocke which, in turn, derives from the medieval Latin word clocca, which ultimately derives from Celtic and is cognate with French, Latin, and German words that mean bell. The passage of the hours at sea were marked by bells, and denoted the time (see ship's bell). The hours were marked by bells in abbeys as well as at sea.

Chip-scale atomic clocks, such as this one unveiled in 2004, are expected to greatly improve GPS location.[35]

Clocks can range from watches, to more exotic varieties such as the Clock of the Long Now. They can be driven by a variety of means, including gravity, springs, and various forms of electrical power, and regulated by a variety of means such as a pendulum.

Alarm clocks first appeared in Ancient Greece around 250 B.C. with a water clock that would set off a whistle. This idea was later mechanized by Levi Hutchins and Seth E. Thomas.[34]

A chronometer is a portable timekeeper that meets certain precision standards. Initially, the term was used to refer to the marine chronometer, a timepiece used to determine longitude by means of celestial navigation, a precision firstly achieved by John Harrison. More recently, the term has also been applied to the chronometer watch, a watch that meets precision standards set by the Swiss agency COSC.

The most accurate timekeeping devices are atomic clocks, which are accurate to seconds in many millions of years,[36] and are used to calibrate other clocks and timekeeping instruments. Atomic clocks use the frequency of electronic transitions in certain atoms to measure the second. One of the most common atoms used is caesium, most modern atomic clocks probe caesium with microwaves to determine the frequency of these electron vibrations.[37] Since 1967, the International System of Measurements bases its unit of time, the second, on the properties of caesium atoms. SI defines the second as 9,192,631,770 cycles of the radiation that corresponds to the transition between two electron spin energy levels of the ground state of the 133Cs atom.

Today, the Global Positioning System in coordination with the Network Time Protocol can be used to synchronize timekeeping systems across the globe.

In medieval philosophical writings, the atom was a unit of time referred to as the smallest possible division of time. The earliest known occurrence in English is in Byrhtferth's Enchiridion (a science text) of 1010–1012,[38] where it was defined as 1/564 of a momentum (1½ minutes),[39] and thus equal to 15/94 of a second. It was used in the computus, the process of calculating the date of Easter.

截至May 2010年 (May 2010-Missing required parameter 1=month!), the smallest time interval uncertainty in direct measurements is on the order of 12 attoseconds (1.2 × 10−17 seconds), about 3.7 × 1026 Planck times.[40]

List of units

[编辑]
Units of time
Unit Length, Duration and Size Notes
instant varies loosely speaking, zero time (colloquially the term may be used in other ways)
Planck time unit 5.39 x 10−44 s The duration light takes to travel one Planck length. Theorized to be the smallest duration measurement that will ever be possible, roughly 10−43 seconds.
yoctosecond 10−24 s
jiffy (quantum physics) about 3 × 10−24 The duration light takes to travel one fermi (10−15 m, about the size of a nucleon) in a vacuum.
zeptosecond 10−21 s
attosecond 10−18 s shortest duration now measurable
femtosecond 10−15 s pulse duration on fastest lasers
picosecond 10−12 s
nanosecond 10−9 s duration for molecules to fluoresce
shake 10−8 s 10 nanoseconds. Also a casual term for a short duration.
microsecond 10−6 s
millisecond 0.001 s shortest duration unit used on stopwatches
centisecond 0.01 s used on some stopwatches
jiffy (electronics) ~1/50 s to 1/60 s Used to measure the duration between alternating power cycles. Also a casual term for a short duration
decisecond 0.1 s Used on some stopwatches
second 1 s SI base unit
decasecond 10 seconds
half a minute 30 seconds
minute 60 seconds
moment (historical) 1/40th of an hour? (90 seconds) used by Medieval Western European computists.[41]
hectosecond 100 seconds 1 minute and 40 seconds
5 minutes 300 seconds All the numbers on an analog clock are 5 minutes apart
centiday 864 seconds traditional Chinese unit of decimal time duration, usually 1/100 of a day, apart by 100 ke(scales) on the sundial and the ruler of water clock, i.e. 14 minutes and 24 seconds. (Nearly 1/4 of an hour. Similar to the English word "quarter" as in "a quarter past six", i.e. 6:15)
kilosecond 1,000 seconds 16 minutes and 40 seconds
point 24 minutes Traditional Chinese time unit, usually 1/60 of a day.
hour 60 minutes
dualhour 2 hours Traditional time unit, 1/12 of a day. apart by 12 shi on the sundial.
deciday 2.4 hours Traditional unit of decimal time duration, 1/10 of a day. apart by geng
day 24 hours longest unit used on stopwatches and countdowns
week 7 days Also called sennight
megasecond 1,000,000 seconds About 11.6 days
fortnight 14 days 2 weeks (more common in Great Britain)
lunar month 27.2–29.5 days Various definitions of lunar month exist.
February 28–29 days This month gets an extra day in a leap year
common month 30–31 days Often 30 days for financial and other calculations.
quarter and season 3 months The duration of any of the four calendar seasons; winter, spring, summer and autumn.
year 12 months
common year 365 days 52 weeks + 1 day
tropical year 365.24219 days[42] average
Gregorian year 365.2425 days[43] average
Julian year 365.25 days
sidereal year 365.256363004 days
leap year 366 days 52 weeks + 2 days
biennium 2 years A unit of time duration commonly used by legislatures
triennium 3 years
Olympiad 4 year cycle
lustrum 5 years
decade 10 years
Indiction 15 year cycle
generation varies about 17–36 years for humans, but some are more extreme
gigasecond 1,000,000,000 seconds About 31.7 years
jubilee 50 years
Lifespan 85 or 82 years how long (on average) people live
century 100 years
millennium 1,000 years also called "kiloannum"
terasecond 1012 seconds About 31,700 years
megaannum 1,000,000 years 1 million years
age varies on the geological timescale, some millions of years[44]
epoch varies on the geological timescale, tens of millions of years[44]
petasecond 1015 seconds About 31.7 million years
era varies on the geological timescale, several hundred millions of years[44]
galactic year Approximately 230 million years[45] The duration it takes the Sun to orbit the center of the Milky Way galaxy once.
eon varies on the geological timescale, 500 million years or more.[44] Also "an indefinite and very long period of time".[46]
gigaannum 1,000,000,000 years A billion years (109)
Our star's lifespan 12,000,000,000 years Is how long the sun will live
exasecond 1018 seconds roughly 31.7 x 109 years, more than twice the age of the universe (on current estimates)
teraannum 1,000,000,000,000 years A trillion years (1012)
zettasecond 1021 seconds About 31.7 x 1012 years
petaannum 1,000,000,000,000,000 years A quadrillion years (1015)
yottasecond 1024 seconds About 31.7 x 1015 years
cosmological decade varies 10 times the length of the previous cosmological decade, with CÐ 1 beginning either 10 seconds or 10 years after the Big Bang, depending on the definition.

Definitions and standards

[编辑]

Originally the second was defined as 1/86,400 of the mean solar day, which is the year-average of the solar day, being the time interval between two successive noons, i.e., the time interval between two successive passages of the sun across the meridian. In 1874 the British Association for the Advancement of Science introduced the CGS (centimetre/gramme/second system) combining fundamental units of length, mass and time. This second is "elastic", because tidal friction is slowing the earth's rotation rate. For use in calculating ephemerides of celestial motion, therefore, in 1952 astronomers introduced the "ephemeris second", currently defined as

the fraction 1/31,556,925.9747 of the tropical year for 1900 January 0 at 12 hours ephemeris time.

[47]

The CGS system has been superseded by the Système international. The SI base unit for time is the SI second. The International System of Quantities, which incorporates the SI, also defines larger units of time equal to fixed integer multiples of one second (1 s), such as the minute, hour and day. These are not part of the SI, but may be used alongside the SI. Other units of time such as the month and the year are not equal to fixed multiples of 1 s, and instead exhibit significant variations in duration.[48]

The official SI definition of the second is as follows:[48][49]

The second is the duration of 9,192,631,770 periods of the radiation corresponding to the transition between the two hyperfine levels of the ground state of the caesium 133 atom.

At its 1997 meeting, the CIPM affirmed that this definition refers to a caesium atom in its ground state at a temperature of 0 K.[48]

The current definition of the second, coupled with the current definition of the metre, is based on the special theory of relativity, which affirms our spacetime to be a Minkowski space. The definition of the second in mean solar time, however, is unchanged.

World time

[编辑]

While in theory, the concept of a single world-wide universal time-scale may have been conceived of many centuries ago, in practicality the technical ability to create and maintain such a time-scale did not become possible until the mid-19th century. The timescale adopted was Greenwich Mean Time, created in 1847. A few countries have replaced it with Coordinated Universal Time, UTC.

History of the development of UTC

[编辑]

With the advent of the industrial revolution, a greater understanding and agreement on the nature of time itself became increasingly necessary and helpful. In 1847 in Britain, Greenwich Mean Time (GMT) was first created for use by the British railways, the British navy, and the British shipping industry. Using telescopes, GMT was calibrated to the mean solar time at the Royal Observatory, Greenwich in the UK.

As international commerce continued to increase throughout Europe, in order to achieve a more efficiently functioning modern society, an agreed upon, and highly accurate international standard of time measurement became necessary. In order to find or determine such a time-standard, three steps had to be followed:

  1. An internationally agreed upon time-standard had to be defined.
  2. This new time-standard then had to be consistently and accurately measured.
  3. The new time-standard then had to be freely shared and distributed around the world.

The development of what is now known as UTC time came about historically as an effort which first began as a collaboration between 41 nations, officially agreed to and signed at the International Meridian Conference, in Washington D.C. in 1984 [50]

Amongst these 41 nations represented at this conference, the advanced time-technologies that had already come into use in Britain were fundamental components of the agreed upon method of arriving at a universal and agreed upon international time.

In 1928 the modern day descendant of GMT (though slightly less accurate than UTC) was defined by the International Astronomical Union as Universal Time (UT). Even to the present day, UT is still based on an international telescopic system. Observations at the Greenwich Observatory itself ceased in 1954, though the location is still used as the basis for the coordinate system. Because the rotational period of Earth is not perfectly constant, the duration of a second would vary if calibrated to a telescope-based standard like GMT or UT—in which a second was defined as a fraction of a day or year. The terms "GMT" and "Greenwich Mean Time" are sometimes used informally to refer to UT, however GMT and UTC are not the same thing, and the most accurate description of the most commonly used international time standard is now UTC, and is no longer "GMT".

For the better part of the first century following the "International Meridian Conference," until 1960, the methods and definitions of time-keeping that had been laid out at the Conference proved to be adequate to meet time tracking needs of society. Still, with the advent of the "electronic revolution" in the latter half of the 20th century, the technologies that had been available at the time of the Convention of the Metre, proved to be in need of further refinement in order to meet the needs of the ever increasing precision that the "electronic revolution" had begun to require. Therefore, in 1960, due to irregularities that had been found in the length of a solar year over time, it was agreed upon that the solar year, 1900 would thenceforth serve as the "reference year" for all future computations and definitions of the exact length of a year, and by inference, of a second-of-time. This new definition of a second-of-time, based on the reference year of 1900, came to be known as the ephemeris-second.[51]

Once a more exact and measurable definition of a second-of-time had been agreed upon, known as the ephemeris-second, in 1967, the new and more easily measured technology of the atomic clock resulted in the agreed upon definition of the si-second, now based directly on the atomic clock equivalent of the ephemeris-second.[52] The si-second (Standard Internationale second) has stood since 1967 as the internationally recognized fundamental building-block to be used for the computation and measurement of time, and is based directly on the measurement of the atomic-clock observation of the frequency oscillation of cesium atoms. Atomic clocks do not measure nuclear decay rates, which is a common misperception, but rather measure a certain natural vibrational frequency of Cesium-133.[53]

Current application of UTC

[编辑]

The most commonly used standard of time is currently what is typically referred to as UTC Time. This time-standard is based on the si-second, which was first defined in 1967, and is based on the use of atomic clocks. Some other less used but closely related time-standards include International Atomic Time (TAI), Terrestrial Time, and Barycentric Dynamical Time.

Between 1967 and 1971, UTC was periodically adjusted by fractional "leap seconds" in order to adjust and refine for various temporal aberrations that were subsequently discovered. After 1 January 1972, UTC time has been defined as being offset from the original 1967 UTC time by a whole-number of seconds, changing only when a leap second is added to keep clock time synchronized with the rotation of the Earth.

The Global Positioning System also broadcasts a very precise time signal worldwide, along with instructions for converting GPS time to UTC. GPS-time is based on, and regularly synchronized with or from, UTC-time.

Earth is split up into a number of time zones. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from UTC. In many locations these offsets vary twice yearly due to daylight saving time transitions. While a few governments still legally define their national times as being based upon GMT, most major governments have now redefined their national times as being based directly upon UTC.

Time conversions

[编辑]

These conversions are accurate at the millisecond level for time systems involving earth rotation (UT1 & TT). Conversions between atomic time systems (TAI, GPS, and UTC) are accurate at the microsecond level.

System Description UT1 UTC TT TAI GPS
UT1 Mean Solar Time UT1 UTC = UT1 - DUT1 TT = UT1 + 32.184 s + LS - DUT1 TAI = UT1 - DUT1 + LS GPS = UT1 - DUT1 + LS - 19 s
UTC Civil Time UT1 = UTC + DUT1 UTC TT = UTC + 32.184 s + LS TAI = UTC + LS GPS = UTC + LS - 19 s
TT Terrestrial (Ephemeris) Time UT1 = TT - 32.184 s - LS + DUT1 UTC = TT - 32.184 s - LS TT TAI = TT - 32.184 s GPS = TT - 51.184 s
TAI Atomic Time UT1 = TAI + DUT1 - LS UTC = TAI - LS TT = TAI + 32.184 s TAI GPS = TAI - 19 s
GPS GPS Time UT1 = GPS + DUT1 - LS + 19 s UTC = GPS - LS + 19 s TT = GPS + 51.184 s TAI = GPS + 19 s GPS

Definitions:

  1. LS = TAI - UTC = Leap Seconds from http://maia.usno.navy.mil/ser7/tai-utc.dat
  2. DUT1 = UT1 - UTC from http://maia.usno.navy.mil/ser7/ser7.dat or http://maia.usno.navy.mil/search/search.html

Sidereal time

[编辑]

Sidereal time is the measurement of time relative to a distant star (instead of solar time that is relative to the sun). It is used in astronomy to predict when a star will be overhead. Due to the orbit of the earth around the sun a sidereal day is about 4 minutes (1/366th) less than a solar day.

Chronology

[编辑]

Another form of time measurement consists of studying the past. Events in the past can be ordered in a sequence (creating a chronology), and can be put into chronological groups (periodization). One of the most important systems of periodization is the geologic time scale, which is a system of periodizing the events that shaped the Earth and its life. Chronology, periodization, and interpretation of the past are together known as the study of history.

Time-like concepts: terminology

[编辑]

The term "time" is generally used for many close but different concepts, including:

  • instant[54] as an object—one point on the time axes. Being an object, it has no value;
  • time interval[55] as an object—part of the time axes limited by two instants. Being an object, it has no value;
  • date[56] as a quantity characterizing an instant. As a quantity, it has a value which may be expressed in a variety of ways, for example "2014-04-26T09:42:36,75" in ISO standard format, or more colloquially such as "today, 9:42 a.m.";
  • duration[57] as a quantity characterizing a time interval.[58] As a quantity, it has a value, such as a number of minutes, or may be described in terms of the quantities (such as times and dates) of its beginning and end.

Religion

[编辑]
Hindu units of time shown logarithmically

Linear and cyclical time

[编辑]

Ancient cultures such as Incan, Mayan, Hopi, and other Native American Tribes - plus the Babylonians, Ancient Greeks, Hinduism, Buddhism, Jainism, and others - have a concept of a wheel of time: they regard time as cyclical and quantic,How polynomials relate to this[需要解释] consisting of repeating ages that happen to every being of the Universe between birth and extinction.[来源请求]

In general, the Islamic and Judeo-Christian world-view regards time as linear[59] and directional,[60] beginning with the act of creation by God. The traditional Christian view sees time ending, teleologically,[61] with the eschatological end of the present order of things, the "end time".

In the Old Testament book Ecclesiastes, traditionally ascribed to Solomon (970–928 BC), time (as the Hebrew word עדן, זמן `iddan(time) zĕman(season) is often translated) was traditionally regarded[谁说的?] as a medium for the passage of predestined events.[来源请求] (Another word, زمان" זמן" zamān, meant time fit for an event, and is used as the modern Arabic, Persian, and Hebrew equivalent to the English word "time".)

Time in Greek mythology

[编辑]

The Greek language denotes two distinct principles, Chronos and Kairos. The former refers to numeric, or chronological, time. The latter, literally "the right or opportune moment", relates specifically to metaphysical or Divine time. In theology, Kairos is qualitative, as opposed to quantitative.

In Greek mythology, Chronos (Ancient Greek: Χρόνος) is identified as the Personification of Time. His name in Greek means "time" and is alternatively spelled Chronus (Latin spelling) or Khronos. Chronos is usually portrayed as an old, wise man with a long, gray beard, such as "Father Time". Some English words whose etymological root is khronos/chronos include chronology, chronometer, chronic, anachronism, synchronize, and chronicle.

Time in Kabbalah

[编辑]

According to Kabbalists, “time” is a paradox[62] and an illusion.[63] Both the future and the past are recognized to be combined and simultaneously present.

Philosophy

[编辑]

Two distinct viewpoints on time divide many prominent philosophers. One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the universe, a dimension in which events occur in sequence. Sir Isaac Newton subscribed to this realist view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as Newtonian time.[16] An opposing view is that time does not refer to any kind of actually existing dimension that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead an intellectual concept (together with space and number) that enables humans to sequence and compare events.[64] This second view, in the tradition of Gottfried Leibniz[17] and Immanuel Kant,[18][19] holds that space and time "do not exist in and of themselves, but ... are the product of the way we represent things", because we can know objects only as they appear to us.

The Vedas, the earliest texts on Indian philosophy and Hindu philosophy dating back to the late 2nd millennium BC, describe ancient Hindu cosmology, in which the universe goes through repeated cycles of creation, destruction and rebirth, with each cycle lasting 4,320 million years.[65] Ancient Greek philosophers, including Parmenides and Heraclitus, wrote essays on the nature of time.[66] Plato, in the Timaeus, identified time with the period of motion of the heavenly bodies. Aristotle, in Book IV of his Physica defined time as 'number of movement in respect of the before and after'.[67]

In Book 11 of his Confessions, St. Augustine of Hippo ruminates on the nature of time, asking, "What then is time? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one that asketh, I know not." He begins to define time by what it is not rather than what it is,[68] an approach similar to that taken in other negative definitions. However, Augustine ends up calling time a “distention” of the mind (Confessions 11.26) by which we simultaneously grasp the past in memory, the present by attention, and the future by expectation.

In contrast to ancient Greek philosophers who believed that the universe had an infinite past with no beginning, medieval philosophers and theologians developed the concept of the universe having a finite past with a beginning. This view is shared by Abrahamic faiths as they believe time started by creation, therefore the only thing being infinite is God and everything else, including time, is finite.

Isaac Newton believed in absolute space and absolute time; Leibniz believed that time and space are relational.[69] The differences between Leibniz's and Newton's interpretations came to a head in the famous Leibniz–Clarke correspondence.

Time is not an empirical concept. For neither co-existence nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition we could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in succession.
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781), trans. Vasilis Politis (London: Dent., 1991), p.54.

Immanuel Kant, in the Critique of Pure Reason, described time as an a priori intuition that allows us (together with the other a priori intuition, space) to comprehend sense experience.[70] With Kant, neither space nor time are conceived as substances, but rather both are elements of a systematic mental framework that necessarily structures the experiences of any rational agent, or observing subject. Kant thought of time as a fundamental part of an abstract conceptual framework, together with space and number, within which we sequence events, quantify their duration, and compare the motions of objects. In this view, time does not refer to any kind of entity that "flows," that objects "move through," or that is a "container" for events. Spatial measurements are used to quantify the extent of and distances between objects, and temporal measurements are used to quantify the durations of and between events. Time was designated by Kant as the purest possible schema of a pure concept or category.

Henri Bergson believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as Duration. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.[71]

According to Martin Heidegger we do not exist inside time, we are time. Hence, the relationship to the past is a present awareness of having been, which allows the past to exist in the present. The relationship to the future is the state of anticipating a potential possibility, task, or engagement. It is related to the human propensity for caring and being concerned, which causes "being ahead of oneself" when thinking of a pending occurrence. Therefore, this concern for a potential occurrence also allows the future to exist in the present. The present becomes an experience, which is qualitative instead of quantitative. Heidegger seems to think this is the way that a linear relationship with time, or temporal existence, is broken or transcended.[72] We are not stuck in sequential time. We are able to remember the past and project into the future—we have a kind of random access to our representation of temporal existence; we can, in our thoughts, step out of (ecstasis) sequential time.[73]

Time as "unreal"

[编辑]

In 5th century BC Greece, Antiphon the Sophist, in a fragment preserved from his chief work On Truth, held that: "Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)." Parmenides went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the paradoxes of his follower Zeno.[74] Time as an illusion is also a common theme in Buddhist thought.[75][76]

J. M. E. McTaggart's 1908 The Unreality of Time argues that, since every event has the characteristic of being both present and not present (i.e., future or past), that time is a self-contradictory idea (see also The flow of time).

These arguments often center around what it means for something to be unreal. Modern physicists generally believe that time is as real as space—though others, such as Julian Barbour in his book The End of Time, argue that quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless realm containing every possible now or momentary configuration of the universe, called 'platonia' by Barbour.[77]

A modern philosophical theory called presentism views the past and the future as human-mind interpretations of movement instead of real parts of time (or "dimensions") which coexist with the present. This theory rejects the existence of all direct interaction with the past or the future, holding only the present as tangible. This is one of the philosophical arguments against time travel. This contrasts with eternalism (all time: present, past and future, is real) and the growing block theory (the present and the past are real, but the future is not).

Physical definition

[编辑]

Template:Classical mechanics

Until Einstein's reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space, time was considered to be the same everywhere in the universe, with all observers measuring the same time interval for any event.[78] Non-relativistic classical mechanics is based on this Newtonian idea of time.

Einstein, in his special theory of relativity,[79] postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer.

The theory of special relativity finds a convenient formulation in Minkowski spacetime, a mathematical structure that combines three dimensions of space with a single dimension of time. In this formalism, distances in space can be measured by how long light takes to travel that distance, e.g., a light-year is a measure of distance, and a meter is now defined in terms of how far light travels in a certain amount of time. Two events in Minkowski spacetime are separated by an invariant interval, which can be either space-like, light-like, or time-like. Events that have a time-like separation cannot be simultaneous in any frame of reference, there must be a temporal component (and possibly a spatial one) to their separation. Events that have a space-like separation will be simultaneous in some frame of reference, and there is no frame of reference in which they do not have a spatial separation. Different observers may calculate different distances and different time intervals between two events, but the invariant interval between the events is independent of the observer (and his velocity).

Classical mechanics

[编辑]

In non-relativistic classical mechanics, Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works sufficiently well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience. In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. Einstein resolved these problems by invoking a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the result that observers in motion relative to one another measure different elapsed times for the same event.

Two-dimensional space depicted in three-dimensional spacetime. The past and future light cones are absolute, the "present" is a relative concept different for observers in relative motion.

Spacetime

[编辑]

Time has historically been closely related with space, the two together merging into spacetime in Einstein's special relativity and general relativity. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the spatial reference frame of the observer, and the human perception as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks are different for observers in relative motion. For example, if a spaceship carrying a clock flies through space at (very nearly) the speed of light, its crew does not notice a change in the speed of time on board their vessel because everything traveling at the same speed slows down at the same rate (including the clock, the crew's thought processes, and the functions of their bodies). However, to a stationary observer watching the spaceship fly by, the spaceship appears flattened in the direction it is traveling and the clock on board the spaceship appears to move very slowly.

On the other hand, the crew on board the spaceship also perceives the observer as slowed down and flattened along the spaceship's direction of travel, because both are moving at very nearly the speed of light relative to each other. Because the outside universe appears flattened to the spaceship, the crew perceives themselves as quickly traveling between regions of space that (to the stationary observer) are many light years apart. This is reconciled by the fact that the crew's perception of time is different from the stationary observer's; what seems like seconds to the crew might be hundreds of years to the stationary observer. In either case, however, causality remains unchanged: the past is the set of events that can send light signals to an entity and the future is the set of events to which an entity can send light signals.[80][81][82]

Time dilation

[编辑]
Relativity of simultaneity: Event B is simultaneous with A in the green reference frame, but it occurred before in the blue frame, and occurs later in the red frame.

Einstein showed in his thought experiments that people travelling at different speeds, while agreeing on cause and effect, measure different time separations between events, and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are typically minute in the human experience, the effect becomes much more pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. Many subatomic particles exist for only a fixed fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but some that travel close to the speed of light can be measured to travel farther and survive much longer than expected (a muon is one example). According to the special theory of relativity, in the high-speed particle's frame of reference, it exists, on the average, for a standard amount of time known as its mean lifetime, and the distance it travels in that time is zero, because its velocity is zero. Relative to a frame of reference at rest, time seems to "slow down" for the particle. Relative to the high-speed particle, distances seem to shorten. Einstein showed how both temporal and spatial dimensions can be altered (or "warped") by high-speed motion.

Einstein (The Meaning of Relativity): "Two events taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relatively to K, which register the same simultaneously."

Einstein wrote in his book, Relativity, that simultaneity is also relative, i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference.

Relativistic time versus Newtonian time

[编辑]
Views of spacetime along the world line of a rapidly accelerating observer in a relativistic universe. The events ("dots") that pass the two diagonal lines in the bottom half of the image (the past light cone of the observer in the origin) are the events visible to the observer.

The animations visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At the heart of these differences are the Galilean and Lorentz transformations applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively.

In the figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the spacetime trajectory ("world line") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime.

The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer. Note how in both pictures the view of spacetime changes when the observer accelerates.

In the Newtonian description these changes are such that time is absolute:[83] the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e., whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer).

However, in the relativistic description the observability of events is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "light cone" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of absolute time is no longer applicable: events move up-and-down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer.

Arrow of time

[编辑]

Time appears to have a direction—the past lies behind, fixed and immutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet for the most part the laws of physics do not specify an arrow of time, and allow any process to proceed both forward and in reverse. This is generally a consequence of time being modeled by a parameter in the system being analyzed, where there is no "proper time": the direction of the arrow of time is sometimes arbitrary. Examples of this include the Second law of thermodynamics, which states that entropy must increase over time (see Entropy); the cosmological arrow of time, which points away from the Big Bang, CPT symmetry, and the radiative arrow of time, caused by light only traveling forwards in time (see light cone). In particle physics, the violation of CP symmetry implies that there should be a small counterbalancing time asymmetry to preserve CPT symmetry as stated above. The standard description of measurement in quantum mechanics is also time asymmetric (see Measurement in quantum mechanics).

Quantized time

[编辑]

Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories (the Standard Model of Particles and Interactions and General Relativity) time is not quantized.

Planck time (~ 5.4 × 10−44 seconds) is the unit of time in the system of natural units known as Planck units. Current established physical theories are believed to fail at this time scale, and many physicists expect that the Planck time might be the smallest unit of time that could ever be measured, even in principle. Tentative physical theories that describe this time scale exist; see for instance loop quantum gravity.

Time and the Big Bang theory

[编辑]

Stephen Hawking in particular has addressed a connection between time and the Big Bang. In A Brief History of Time and elsewhere, Hawking says that even if time did not begin with the Big Bang and there were another time frame before the Big Bang, no information from events then would be accessible to us, and nothing that happened then would have any effect upon the present time-frame.[84] Upon occasion, Hawking has stated that time actually began with the Big Bang, and that questions about what happened before the Big Bang are meaningless.[85][86][87] This less-nuanced, but commonly repeated formulation has received criticisms from philosophers such as Aristotelian philosopher Mortimer J. Adler.[88][89]

Scientists have come to some agreement on descriptions of events that happened 10−35 seconds after the Big Bang, but generally agree that descriptions about what happened before one Planck time (5 × 10−44 seconds) after the Big Bang are likely to remain pure speculation.

Speculative physics beyond the Big Bang

[编辑]
A graphical representation of the expansion of the universe with the inflationary epoch represented as the dramatic expansion of the metric seen on the left

While the Big Bang model is well established in cosmology, it is likely to be refined in the future. Little is known about the earliest moments of the universe's history. The Penrose–Hawking singularity theorems require the existence of a singularity at the beginning of cosmic time. However, these theorems assume that general relativity is correct, but general relativity must break down before the universe reaches the Planck temperature, and a correct treatment of quantum gravity may avoid the singularity.[90]

If inflation has indeed occurred, it is likely that there are parts of the universe so distant that they cannot be observed in principle, as exponential expansion would push large regions of space beyond our observable horizon.

Some proposals, each of which entails untested hypotheses, are:

  • Models including the Hartle–Hawking boundary condition in which the whole of space-time is finite; the Big Bang does represent the limit of time, but without the need for a singularity.[91]
  • Brane cosmology models[92] in which inflation is due to the movement of branes in string theory; the pre-big bang model; the ekpyrotic model, in which the Big Bang is the result of a collision between branes; and the cyclic model, a variant of the ekpyrotic model in which collisions occur periodically.[93][94][95]
  • Chaotic inflation, in which inflation events start here and there in a random quantum-gravity foam, each leading to a bubble universe expanding from its own big bang.[96]

Proposals in the last two categories see the Big Bang as an event in a much larger and older universe, or multiverse, and not the literal beginning.

Time travel

[编辑]

Time travel is the concept of moving backwards or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through space, and different from the normal "flow" of time to an earthbound observer. In this view, all points in time (including future times) "persist" in some way. Time travel has been a plot device in fiction since the 19th century. Traveling backwards in time has never been verified, presents many theoretic problems, and may be an impossibility.[97] Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a time machine.

A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of causality; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of a temporal paradox. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between branch points, parallel realities, or universes.

Another solution to the problem of causality-based temporal paradoxes is that such paradoxes cannot arise simply because they have not arisen. As illustrated in numerous works of fiction, free will either ceases to exist in the past or the outcomes of such decisions are predetermined. As such, it would not be possible to enact the grandfather paradox because it is a historical fact that your grandfather was not killed before his child (your parent) was conceived. This view doesn't simply hold that history is an unchangeable constant, but that any change made by a hypothetical future time traveler would already have happened in his or her past, resulting in the reality that the traveler moves from. More elaboration on this view can be found in the Novikov self-consistency principle.

Time perception

[编辑]
Philosopher and psychologist William James

The specious present refers to the time duration wherein one's perceptions are considered to be in the present. The experienced present is said to be ‘specious’ in that, unlike the objective present, it is an interval and not a durationless instant. The term specious present was first introduced by the psychologist E.R. Clay, and later developed by William James.[98]

Biopsychology

[编辑]

The brain's judgment of time is known to be a highly distributed system, including at least the cerebral cortex, cerebellum and basal ganglia as its components. One particular component, the suprachiasmatic nuclei, is responsible for the circadian (or daily) rhythm, while other cell clusters appear capable of shorter-range (ultradian) timekeeping.

Psychoactive drugs can impair the judgment of time. Stimulants can lead both humans and rats to overestimate time intervals,[99][100] while depressants can have the opposite effect.[101] The level of activity in the brain of neurotransmitters such as dopamine and norepinephrine may be the reason for this.[102] Such chemicals will either excite or inhibit the firing of neurons in the brain, with a greater firing rate allowing the brain to register the occurrence of more events within a given interval (speed up time) and a decreased firing rate reducing the brain's capacity to distinguish events occurring within a given interval (slow down time).[103]

Mental chronometry is the use of response time in perceptual-motor tasks to infer the content, duration, and temporal sequencing of cognitive operations.

Development of awareness and understanding of time in children

[编辑]

Children's expanding cognitive abilities allow them to understand time more clearly. Two- and three-year-olds' understanding of time is mainly limited to "now and not now." Five- and six-year-olds can grasp the ideas of past, present, and future. Seven- to ten-year-olds can use clocks and calendars.[104]

Alterations

[编辑]

In addition to psychoactive drugs, judgments of time can be altered by temporal illusions (like the kappa effect),[105] age,[106] and hypnosis.[107] The sense of time is impaired in some people with neurological diseases such as Parkinson's disease and attention deficit disorder.

Psychologists assert that time seems to go faster with age, but the literature on this age-related perception of time remains controversial.[108] Those who support this notion argue that young people, having more excitatory neurotransmitters, are able to cope with faster external events.[103]

Use of time

[编辑]

In sociology and anthropology, time discipline is the general name given to social and economic rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the social currency and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others. Arlie Russell Hochschild[109][110] and Norbert Elias[111] have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective.

The use of time is an important issue in understanding human behavior, education, and travel behavior. Time-use research is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with technology, as the television or the Internet created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in transport, has been observed to be about 20–30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period.

Time management is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task requires and when it must be completed, and adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so it is done in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools.

A sequence of events, or series of events, is a sequence of items, facts, events, actions, changes, or procedural steps, arranged in time order (chronological order), often with causality relationships among the items.[112][113][114] Because of causality, cause precedes effect, or cause and effect may appear together in a single item, but effect never precedes cause. A sequence of events can be presented in text, tables, charts, or timelines. The description of the items or events may include a timestamp. A sequence of events that includes the time along with place or location information to describe a sequential path may be referred to as a world line.

Uses of a sequence of events include stories,[115] historical events (chronology), directions and steps in procedures,[116] and timetables for scheduling activities. A sequence of events may also be used to help describe processes in science, technology, and medicine. A sequence of events may be focused on past events (e.g., stories, history, chronology), on future events that must be in a predetermined order (e.g., plans, schedules, procedures, timetables), or focused on the observation of past events with the expectation that the events will occur in the future (e.g., processes). The use of a sequence of events occurs in fields as diverse as machines (cam timer), documentaries (Seconds From Disaster), law (choice of law), computer simulation (discrete event simulation), and electric power transmission[117] (sequence of events recorder). A specific example of a sequence of events is the timeline of the Fukushima Daiichi nuclear disaster.

See also

[编辑]
Time's mortal aspect is personified in this bronze statue by Charles van der Stappen

Books

[编辑]

Organizations

[编辑]

Leading scholarly organizations for researchers on the history and technology of time and timekeeping

References

[编辑]
  1. ^ Oxford Dictionaries:Time. Oxford University Press. 2011 [18 December 2011]. the indefinite continued progress of existence and events in the past, present, and future regarded as a whole 
  2. ^ 2.0 2.1 2.2
    • Webster's New World College Dictionary. 2010 [9 April 2011]. 1.indefinite, unlimited duration in which things are considered as happening in the past, present, or future; every moment there has ever been or ever will be… a system of measuring duration 2.the period between two events or during which something exists, happens, or acts; measured or measurable interval 
    • The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary. 2002 [9 April 2011]. A duration or relation of events expressed in terms of past, present, and future, and measured in units such as minutes, hours, days, months, or years. 
    • Collins Language.com. HarperCollins. 2011 [18 December 2011]. 1. The continuous passage of existence in which events pass from a state of potentiality in the future, through the present, to a state of finality in the past. 2. physics a quantity measuring duration, usually with reference to a periodic process such as the rotation of the earth or the frequency of electromagnetic radiation emitted from certain atoms. In classical mechanics, time is absolute in the sense that the time of an event is independent of the observer. According to the theory of relativity it depends on the observer's frame of reference. Time is considered as a fourth coordinate required, along with three spatial coordinates, to specify an event. 
    • The American Heritage Science Dictionary @dictionary.com. 2002 [9 April 2011]. 1. A continuous, measurable quantity in which events occur in a sequence proceeding from the past through the present to the future. 2a. An interval separating two points of this quantity; a duration. 2b. A system or reference frame in which such intervals are measured or such quantities are calculated. 
    • Eric Weisstein's World of Science. 2007 [9 April 2011]. A quantity used to specify the order in which events occurred and measure the amount by which one event preceded or followed another. In special relativity, ct (where c is the speed of light and t is time), plays the role of a fourth dimension. 
  3. ^ Time. The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language Fourth (Houghton Mifflin Company). 2011. A nonspatial continuum in which events occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future. 
  4. ^ Merriam-Webster Dictionary the measured or measurable period during which an action, process, or condition exists or continues : duration; a nonspatial continuum which is measured in terms of events that succeed one another from past through present to future
  5. ^ Compact Oxford English Dictionary A limited stretch or space of continued existence, as the interval between two successive events or acts, or the period through which an action, condition, or state continues. (1971)
  6. ^ 6.0 6.1 6.2 6.3
    • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010 [9 April 2011]. Time is what clocks measure. We use time to place events in sequence one after the other, and we use time to compare how long events last... Among philosophers of physics, the most popular short answer to the question "What is physical time?" is that it is not a substance or object but rather a special system of relations among instantaneous events. This working definition is offered by Adolf Grünbaum who applies the contemporary mathematical theory of continuity to physical processes, and he says time is a linear continuum of instants and is a distinguished one-dimensional sub-space of four-dimensional spacetime. 
    • Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary. 2010 [9 April 2011]. 1. the system of those sequential relations that any event has to any other, as past, present, or future; indefinite and continuous duration regarded as that in which events succeed one another.... 3. (sometimes initial capital letter) a system or method of measuring or reckoning the passage of time: mean time; apparent time; Greenwich Time. 4. a limited period or interval, as between two successive events: a long time.... 14. a particular or definite point in time, as indicated by a clock: What time is it? ... 18. an indefinite, frequently prolonged period or duration in the future: Time will tell if what we have done here today was right. 
    • Ivey, Donald G.; Hume, J.N.P. Physics 1. Ronald Press. 1974: 65. Our operational definition of time is that time is what clocks measure. 
  7. ^ 7.0 7.1 7.2 Le Poidevin, Robin. The Experience and Perception of Time. Edward N. Zalta (编). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Winter 2004 [9 April 2011]. 
  8. ^ "Newton did for time what the Greek geometers did for space, idealized it into an exactly measurable dimension." About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution, Paul Davies, p. 31, Simon & Schuster, 1996, ISBN 978-0684818221
  9. ^ Sean M Carroll. From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time. Dutton. 2009. ISBN 978-0-525-95133-9. 
  10. ^ Adam Frank, Cosmology and Culture at the Twilight of the Big Bang, "the time we imagined from the cosmos and the time we imagined into the human experience turn out to be woven so tightly together that we have lost the ability to see each of them for what it is." p. xv, Free Press, 2011, ISBN 978-1439169599
  11. ^ St. Augustine, Confessions, Simon & Brown, 2012, ISBN 978-1613823262
  12. ^ Official Baseball Rules, 2011 Edition. Rules 8.03 and 8.04 (Free PDF download). Major League Baseball. 2011 [7 July 2012]. Rule 8.03 Such preparatory pitches shall not consume more than one minute of time...Rule 8.04 When the bases are unoccupied, the pitcher shall deliver the ball to the batter within 12 seconds...The 12-second timing starts when the pitcher is in possession of the ball and the batter is in the box, alert to the pitcher. The timing stops when the pitcher releases the ball 
  13. ^ Guinness Book of Baseball World Records. Guinness World Records, Ltd. [7 July 2012]. The record for the fastest time for circling the bases is 13.3 seconds, set by Evar Swanson at Columbus, Ohio in 1932...The greatest reliably recorded speed at which a baseball has been pitched is 100.9 mph by Lynn Nolan Ryan (California Angels) at Anaheim Stadium in California on 20 August 1974. 
  14. ^ Zeigler, Kenneth. Getting organized at work : 24 lessons to set goals, establish priorities, and manage your time. McGraw-Hill. 2008. ISBN 9780071591386.  108 pages
  15. ^ Rynasiewicz, Robert : Johns Hopkins University. Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. 12 August 2004 [5 February 2012]. Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation to anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year). 
  16. ^ 16.0 16.1 Markosian, Ned. Time. Edward N. Zalta (编). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition). [23 September 2011]. The opposing view, normally referred to either as “Platonism with Respect to Time” or as “Absolutism with Respect to Time,” has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it. 
  17. ^ 17.0 17.1 17.2 Burnham, Douglas : Staffordshire University. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) Metaphysics – 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2006 [9 April 2011]. First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time. 
  18. ^ 18.0 18.1 Mattey, G. J. : UC Davis. Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis. 22 January 1997 [9 April 2011]. What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The[y] are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, mutatis mutandis, to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition." 
  19. ^ 19.0 19.1 McCormick, Matt : California State University, Sacramento. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) Metaphysics: 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2006 [9 April 2011]. Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the a priori contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues. 
  20. ^ Considine, Douglas M.; Considine, Glenn D. Process instruments and controls handbook 3. McGraw-Hill. 1985: 18–61. ISBN 0-07-012436-1. 
  21. ^ Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ibid. p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature. … The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e., actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of wrong statements."
  22. ^ Carrol, Sean, Chapter One, Section Two, Plume, 2010. From Eternity to Here. ISBN 978-0452296541. As human beings we 'feel' the passage of time. 
  23. ^ Lehar, Steve. (2000). The Function of Conscious Experience: An Analogical Paradigm of Perception and Behavior, Consciousness and Cognition.
  24. ^ Richards, E. G. Mapping Time: The Calendar and its History. Oxford University Press. 1998: 3–5. 
  25. ^ Rudgley, Richard. The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age. New York: Simon & Schuster. 1999: 86–105. 
  26. ^ Van Stone, Mark. "The Maya Long Count Calendar: An Introduction." Archaeoastronomy 24.(2011): 8-11. Academic Search Complete. Web. 20 Feb. 2016.
  27. ^ "French Republican Calendar | Chronology." Encyclopedia Britannica Online. Encyclopedia Britannica, n.d. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.
  28. ^ Barnett, Jo Ellen Time's Pendulum: The Quest to Capture Time—from Sundials to Atomic Clocks Plenum, 1998 ISBN 0-306-45787-3 p.28
  29. ^ Lombardi, Michael A. "Why Is a Minute Divided into 60 Seconds, an Hour into 60 Minutes, Yet There Are Only 24 Hours in a Day?" Scientific American. Springer Nature, 5 Mar. 2007. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.
  30. ^ Barnett, ibid, p.37
  31. ^ Laurence Bergreen, Over the Edge of the World: Magellan's Terrifying Circumnavigation of the Globe, HarperCollins Publishers, 2003, hardcover 480 pages, ISBN 0-06-621173-5
  32. ^ North, J. (2004) God's Clockmaker: Richard of Wallingford and the Invention of Time. Oxbow Books. ISBN 1-85285-451-0
  33. ^ Watson, E (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". Antiquarian Horology 372–384.
  34. ^ 34.0 34.1 "History of Clocks." About.com Inventors. About.com, n.d. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.
  35. ^ NIST Unveils Chip-Scale Atomic Clock. 27 August 2004 [9 June 2011]. 
  36. ^ New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation. Vancouver Sun. 16 February 2008 [9 April 2011]. 
  37. ^ NIST-F1 Cesium Fountain Clock. [24 July 2015]. 
  38. ^ Byrhtferth of Ramsey. Encyclopædia Britannica. 2008 [September 15, 2008]. 
  39. ^ "atom", Oxford English Dictionary, Draft Revision September 2008 (contains relevant citations from Byrhtferth's Enchiridion)
  40. ^ 12 attoseconds is the world record for shortest controllable time. 12 May 2010 [19 April 2012]. 
  41. ^ Bacon, Roger. Opera quaedam hactenus inedita. Harvard University. [5 July 2014]. 
  42. ^ McCarthy, Dennis D.; Seidelmann, P. Kenneth. Time: from Earth rotation to atomic physics. Wiley-VCH. 2009: 18. ISBN 3-527-40780-4.  Extract of page 18
  43. ^ Jones, Floyd Nolen. The Chronology Of The Old Testament 15th. New Leaf Publishing Group. 2005: 287. ISBN 0-89051-416-X.  Extract of page 287
  44. ^ 44.0 44.1 44.2 44.3 Cohen, K.M.; Finney, S.; Gibbard, P.L., International Chronostratigraphic Chart (PDF), International Commission on Stratigraphy, 2013 [23 September 2013] 
  45. ^ NASA - StarChild Question of the Month for February 2000
  46. ^ Aeon - Definition and More from the Free Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Merriam-webster.com. 31 August 2012 [24 September 2013]. 
  47. ^ Whitaker's Almanac 2013 (ed. Ruth Northey), London 2012, p 1131, ISBN 978-1-4081-7207-0.
  48. ^ 48.0 48.1 48.2 Organisation Intergouvernementale de la Convention du Métre. The International System of Units (SI), 7th Edition (PDF). 1998 [9 April 2011]. 
  49. ^ Base unit definitions: Second. NIST. [9 April 2011]. 
  50. ^ Howse 1997,第133–137页.
  51. ^ Leap Seconds. Time Service Department, United States Naval Observatory. [November 22, 2015]. 
  52. ^ W Markowitz, RG Hall, L Essen, JVL Parry; Hall; Essen; Parry. Frequency of cesium in terms of ephemeris time (PDF). Physical Review Letters. 1958, 1 (3): 105–107. Bibcode:1958PhRvL...1..105M. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.1.105. 
  53. ^ Cesium Atoms at Work USNO, downloaded June 28, 2016.
  54. ^ IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-08
  55. ^ IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-010; ISO 80000-3:2006, item 3-7
  56. ^ IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-012: "mark attributed to an instant by means of a specified time scale
  57. ^ IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-013: "range of a time interval (113-01-10)"
  58. ^ ISO 80000-3:2006, item 3-7
  59. ^ Rust, Eric Charles. Religion, Revelation and Reason. Mercer University Press. 1981: 60 [2015-08-20]. ISBN 9780865540583. Profane time, as Eliade points out, is linear. As man dwelt increasingly in the profane and a sense of history developed, the desire to escape into the sacred began to drop in the background. The myths, tied up with cyclic time, were not so easily operative. [...] So secular man became content with his linear time. He could not return to cyclic time and re-enter sacred space though its myths. [...] Just here, as Eliade sees it, a new religious structure became available. In the Judaeo-Christian religions - Judaism, Christianity, Islam - history is taken seriously, and linear time is accepted. The cyclic time of the primordial mythical consciousness has been transformed into the time of profane man, but the mythical consciousness remains. It has been historicized. The Christian mythos and its accompanying ritual are bound up, for example, with history and center in authentic history, especially the Christ-event. Sacred space, the Transcendent Presence, is thus opened up to secular man because it meets him where he is, in the linear flow of secular time. The Christian myth gives such time a beginning in creation, a center in the Christ-event, and an end in the final consummation. 
  60. ^ Betz, Hans Dieter (编). Religion Past & Present: Encyclopedia of Theology and Religion. 4: Dev-Ezr 4. Brill. 2008: 101 [2015-08-20]. ISBN 9789004146884. [...] God produces a creation with a directional time structure [...]. 
  61. ^ Lundin, Roger; Thiselton, Anthony C.; Walhout, Clarence. The Promise of Hermeneutics. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. 1999: 121 [2015-08-20]. ISBN 9780802846358. We need to note the close ties between teleology, eschatology, and utopia. In Christian theology, the understanding of the teleology of particular actions is ultimately related to the teleology of history in general, which is the concern of eschatology. 
  62. ^ Hus, Boʿaz; Pasi, Marco; Von Stuckrad, Kocku. Kabbalah and Modernity: Interpretations, Transformations, Adaptations. BRILL. 2011. ISBN 9004182845. 
  63. ^ Wolfson, Elliot R. Alef, Mem, Tau: Kabbalistic Musings on Time, Truth, and Death. University of California Press. 2006: 111. ISBN 0-520-93231-5.  Extract of page 111
  64. ^ Navratil, Gerhard. Research Trends in Geographic Information Science. Springer Japan. 2009: 217 [9 April 2011]. ISBN 3-540-88243-X. 
  65. ^ Layton, Robert. Who needs the past?: indigenous values and archaeology 2nd. Routledge. 1994: 7 [9 April 2011]. ISBN 0-415-09558-1. , Introduction, p. 7
  66. ^ Dagobert Runes, Dictionary of Philosophy, p. 318
  67. ^ Hardie, R. P.; Gaye, R. K. Physics by Aristotle. MIT. [4 May 2014]. "Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is used in two senses-both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) [...] It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of what is continuous. "
  68. ^ Augustine of Hippo. Confessions. [9 April 2011].  Book 11, Chapter 14.
  69. ^ Gottfried Martin, Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science
  70. ^ Kant, Immanuel. The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition. 1787 [9 April 2011].  translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn, eBooks@Adelaide, 2004
  71. ^ Bergson, Henri (1907) Creative Evolution. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998.
  72. ^ Balslev, Anindita N.; Jitendranath Mohanty. Religion and Time. Studies in the History of Religions, 54. The Netherlands: Brill Academic Publishers. November 1992: 53, 54, 55, 56, 57, 58, and 59. ISBN 978-90-04-09583-0. 
  73. ^ Martin Heidegger. V. Being and Time. 1962: 425. ISBN 978-0-631-19770-6. 
  74. ^ Harry Foundalis. You are about to disappear. [9 April 2011]. 
  75. ^ Huston, Tom. Buddhism and the illusion of time. [9 April 2011]. 
  76. ^ Garfield, Jay L. The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. New York: Oxford University Press. 1995. ISBN 978-0-19-509336-0. 
  77. ^ Time is an illusion?. [9 April 2011]. 
  78. ^ Herman M. Schwartz, Introduction to Special Relativity, McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1968, hardcover 442 pages, see ISBN 0-88275-478-5 (1977 edition), pp. 10–13
  79. ^ A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, H. Minkowski, The Principle of Relativity, Dover Publications, Inc, 2000, softcover 216 pages, ISBN 0-486-60081-5, See pp. 37–65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper.
  80. ^ Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity. YouTube. 30 November 2011 [24 September 2013]. 
  81. ^ Time Travel: Einstein's big idea (Theory of Relativity). YouTube. 9 January 2007 [24 September 2013]. 
  82. ^ Hours, After. 7 Theories on Time That Would Make Doc Brown's Head Explode. Cracked.com. 11 February 2012 [24 September 2013]. 
  83. ^ Knudsen, Jens M.; Hjorth, Poul. Elements of Newtonian Mechanics illustrated. Springer Science & Business Media. 2012: 30. ISBN 978-3-642-97599-8.  Extract of page 30
  84. ^ Hawking, Stephen. The Beginning of Time. University of Cambridge. 1996 [8 July 2012]. Since events before the Big Bang have no observational consequences, one may as well cut them out of the theory, and say that time began at the Big Bang. Events before the Big Bang, are simply not defined, because there's no way one could measure what happened at them. This kind of beginning to the universe, and of time itself, is very different to the beginnings that had been considered earlier. 
  85. ^ Hawking, Stephen. The Beginning of Time. University of Cambridge. 1996 [8 July 2012]. The conclusion of this lecture is that the universe has not existed forever. Rather, the universe, and time itself, had a beginning in the Big Bang, about 15 billion years ago. 
  86. ^ Hawking, Stephen. Professor Stephen Hawking lectures on the origin of the universe. University of Oxford. 27 February 2006 [5 December 2012]. Suppose the beginning of the universe was like the South Pole of the earth, with degrees of latitude playing the role of time. The universe would start as a point at the South Pole. As one moves north, the circles of constant latitude, representing the size of the universe, would expand. To ask what happened before the beginning of the universe would become a meaningless question because there is nothing south of the South Pole. 
  87. ^ Ghandchi, Sam : Editor/Publisher. Space and New Thinking. 16 January 2004 [9 April 2011]. and as Stephen Hawking puts it, asking what was before Big Bang is like asking what is North of North Pole, a meaningless question. 
  88. ^ Adler, Mortimer J., PhD. Natural Theology, Chance, and God. [9 April 2011]. Hawking could have avoided the error of supposing that time had a beginning with the Big Bang if he had distinguished time as it is measured by physicists from time that is not measurable by physicists.... an error shared by many other great physicists in the twentieth century, the error of saying that what cannot be measured by physicists does not exist in reality.  The Great Ideas Today. Encyclopædia Britannica. 1992. 
  89. ^ Adler, Mortimer J., PhD. Natural Theology, Chance, and God. [9 April 2011]. Where Einstein had said that what is not measurable by physicists is of no interest to them, Hawking flatly asserts that what is not measurable by physicists does not exist—has no reality whatsoever.
    With respect to time, that amounts to the denial of psychological time which is not measurable by physicists, and also to everlasting time—time before the Big Bang—which physics cannot measure. Hawking does not know that both Aquinas and Kant had shown that we cannot rationally establish that time is either finite or infinite.
      The Great Ideas Today. Encyclopædia Britannica. 1992. 
  90. ^ Hawking, Stephen & Ellis, G. F. R. The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1973. ISBN 0-521-09906-4. 
  91. ^ J. Hartle and S. W. Hawking. Wave function of the universe. Phys. Rev. D. 1983, 28 (12): 2960. Bibcode:1983PhRvD..28.2960H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.28.2960. 
  92. ^ Langlois, David. Brane cosmology: an introduction. Progress of Theoretical Physics Supplement. 2002, 148: 181. Bibcode:2002PThPS.148..181L. arXiv:hep-th/0209261可免费查阅. doi:10.1143/PTPS.148.181. 
  93. ^ Linde, Andre. Inflationary Theory versus Ekpyrotic/Cyclic Scenario. In: the future of theoretical physics and cosmology. Edited by G. W. Gibbons. 2002: 801. Bibcode:2003ftpc.book..801L. arXiv:hep-th/0205259可免费查阅. 
  94. ^ Recycled Universe: Theory Could Solve Cosmic Mystery. Space.com. 8 May 2006 [9 April 2011]. 
  95. ^ What Happened Before the Big Bang?. [9 April 2011]. (原始内容存档于4 July 2007). 
  96. ^ A. Linde. Eternal chaotic inflation. Mod. Phys. Lett. 1986, A1 (2): 81. Bibcode:1986MPLA....1...81L. doi:10.1142/S0217732386000129.  A. Linde. Eternally existing self-reproducing chaotic inflationary universe. Phys. Lett. 1986, B175 (4): 395–400. Bibcode:1986PhLB..175..395L. doi:10.1016/0370-2693(86)90611-8. 
  97. ^ G. Quznetsov, Prespacetime Journal, March 2010, Vol.1, Issue 2, Page 274-275
  98. ^ Andersen, Holly; Rick Grush. A brief history of time-consciousness: historical precursors to James and Husserl (PDF) 47 (2). Journal of the History of Philosophy: 277–307. 2009 [9 April 2011]. 
  99. ^ Wittmann, M.; Leland DS; Churan J; Paulus MP. Impaired time perception and motor timing in stimulant-dependent subjects (online abstract). Drug Alcohol Depend. 8 October 2007, 90 (2–3): 183–92. PMC 1997301可免费查阅. PMID 17434690. doi:10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2007.03.005. 
  100. ^ Cheng, Ruey-Kuang; Macdonald, Christopher J.; Meck, Warren H. Differential effects of cocaine and ketamine on time estimation: Implications for neurobiological models of interval timing (online abstract). Pharmacology, biochemistry and behavior. 2006, 85 (1): 114–122 [9 April 2011]. PMID 16920182. doi:10.1016/j.pbb.2006.07.019. 
  101. ^ Tinklenberg, Jared R.; Walton T. Roth1; Bert S. Kopell. Marijuana and ethanol: Differential effects on time perception, heart rate, and subjective response. Psychopharmacology. January 1976, 49 (3): 275–279 [9 April 2011]. PMID 826945. doi:10.1007/BF00426830. 
  102. ^ Arzy, Shahar; Istvan Molnar-Szakacs; Olaf Blanke. Self in Time: Imagined Self-Location Influences Neural Activity Related to Mental Time Travel (Abstract). The Journal of Neuroscience. 18 June 2008, 28 (25): 6502–6507 [9 April 2011]. PMID 18562621. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5712-07.2008. 
  103. ^ 103.0 103.1 Carter, Rita. The Human Brain Book. Dorling Kindersley Publishing. 2009: 186–187. ISBN 978-0-7566-5441-2. 
  104. ^ Kennedy-Moore, Eileen. Time Management for Kids. Psychology Today. 28 March 2014 [26 April 2014]. 
  105. ^ Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement
  106. ^ Robert, Adler. Look how time flies... [9 April 2011]. 
  107. ^ Bowers, Kenneth; Brenneman, HA. Hypnosis and the perception of time. International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis (International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis). January 1979, 27 (1): 29–41. PMID 541126. doi:10.1080/00207147908407540. 
  108. ^ Gruber, Ronald P.; Wagner, Lawrence F.; Block, Richard A. Subjective Time Versus Proper (Clock) Time. Buccheri, R.; Di Gesù, V.; Saniga, Metod (编). Studies on the structure of time: from physics to psycho(patho)logy. Springer. 2000: 54 [9 April 2011]. ISBN 0-306-46439-X.  Extract of page 54
  109. ^ Russell Hochschild, Arlie. The time bind: when work becomes home and home becomes work. New York: Metropolitan Books. 1997.  ISBN 9780805044713
  110. ^ Russell Hochschild, Arlie. There's no place like work. New York Times Magazine (The New York Times). 20 April 1997. 
  111. ^ Elias, Norbert. Time: an essay. Oxford, UK Cambridge, USA: Blackwell. 1992. ISBN 9780631157984. 
  112. ^ Sequence - Order of Important Events (PDF). Austin Independent School District. 2009. 
  113. ^ Sequence of Events Worksheets. Reference.com. 
  114. ^ Compiled by David Luckham & Roy Schulte. Event Processing Glossary—Version 2.0. Complex Event Processing. 
  115. ^ Richard Nordquist. narrative. About.com. 
  116. ^ David J. Piasecki. Inventory Accuracy Glossary. AccuracyBook.com (OPS Publishing). 
  117. ^ Utility Communications Architecture (UCA) glossary. NettedAutomation. 

Further reading

[编辑]
[编辑]

Template:Nature nav

Template:SI base quantities